The Flaw in Gödel’s proof of his Incompleteness theorem
Page last updated 10 July 2025
I had previously considered that it would not be feasible to give a brief summary of the flaw in the proof of incompleteness (which you can see online at English translation of Gödel’s original proof) by Kurt Gödel, a proponent of intelligent design (see Statements by Kurt Gödel). But in fact it is possible to pinpoint an intuitive assumption that Gödel makes in his proof which is easily demonstrated to be incorrect and logically invalid. Since the remainder of his proof relies completely on this assumption, this renders the result of the proof invalid.
That assumptive assertion is what Gödel calls Relation 17, and which states:
Gödel previously defined that an italicized word, such as number-string indicates the number calculated by his Gödel numbering function
such that their calculated values are equal when their free variables are equal, and the result of his paper has a complete reliance on this assertion, which is an assumption by Gödel for which he offers no logical justification whatsoever.
It is easily shown that no such equivalence can apply, as follows:
The domain of the free variable
Clearly Gödel did not intend the complete domain of
However, even imposing this restriction does not achieve an equivalence of the two functions. This is because there can be infinitely many expressions that have the same value as any given number, and which are also valid values for the substitution of the free variable of the
But the sequences of symbols “
i.e, a result with 6 prime factors, while even with a formal system that includes the “+” symbol, for the substitution of “
Hence it is quite obvious that there cannot be an equivalence of the
Gödel uses that incorrect assumption of equivalence as an essential part of his proof of his assertion that he calls Proposition V, which renders his Proposition V has logically invalid and the remainder of his proof that follows is likewise completely invalid. See also The Z function assumption.
Perhaps the reader might think that perhaps the above demonstrated error of assumed equivalence is only a curiosity, and perhaps there is some way to circumvent it. But there isn’t. Several people have come up with bizarre ideas in attempts to circumvent the flaw, on web-pages such as on Reddit - Gödel’s flaw, where rhetoric, denial of facts and cherry-picking get more upvotes than scholarly logical argument - I detail some of these in the following section.
Attempts to evade the contradiction
Various people have come up with weird notions in attempts to evade the inherent flaw in Gödel’s proof. In this section I point out the fallacies in some of these bizarre attempts to rescue Gödel’s proof:
Weird idea 1: Gödel didn’t intend an equivalence of his Z function and the Gödel numbering function
This assertion claims that Gödel did not really mean what he actually wrote in his Relation 17:
where Gödel had previously defined that words in italics indicate numbers that are Gödel numbers of the formal sequence that is described by that same word without italics, and a number-string is a sequence of the form
where
It’s not as if there’s any room for nuance in Gödel’s statement in his original German:
and a straightforward word for word translation gives:
which is why all translations of this statement are essentially the same. Furthermore, when van Heijenoort was making a translation of Gödel’s paper, there was frequent communication between them
Over the period 1963-1965, see Kurt Gödel, Collected Works Volume V, Oxford University Press, 2013.
since van Heijenoort wanted Gödel’s full approval of his translation before publication. In view of the fact that in that communication Gödel made numerous finely detailed suggestions, it’s clear that if Gödel had ever thought that there was anything wrong with the statement above regarding
Moreover, further evidence that Gödel intended exactly what he wrote in his relation 17 - rather than making some sort of slip-up - can be seen by his use of the number-theoretic function
And Gödel asserts in his equation 3 of his Proposition 5 that (note that here, for simplicity, the
(A)
where
- relationships between formal expressions, and
- relationships between the Gödel numbers of those expressions,
so there is neccesarily an assumption that
And we note that an expression such as:
(B)
would be assuming that the
(C)
where
where
and
On top of the above, in van Heijenoort’s approved translation, footnote 43 includes the parenthetical addition:
[Precisely stated the final part of this footnote (which refers to a side remark unnecessary for the proof) would read thus: "REPLACEMENT of a VARIABLE by the NUMERAL for p."].
This refers to Gödel’s equation 12,
In short, all the evidence demonstrates that the claim that in reality Gödel did not intend what he had actually written is an absurd fantasy denial of the facts of the matter.
One will also find instances of cherry-picking, for example, remarking on how hundreds of very clever perspicacious mathematicians have examined Gödel's proof and none of them found anything wrong with it. What they omit to add is the concomitant fact that none of these very clever perspicacious mathematicians ever made any negative remark about Gödel's assertion that the function
Further weirdness
Some people try claiming that Gödel could not have intended any sort of equivalence of the two functions on the grounds that the domain of the free variable of
Even further weirdness
In an attempt to show that Gödel did not really intend what he wrote regarding the
Weird idea 2. Gödel meant that there is another function involved
This claim is often associated with a misunderstanding of the term “NUMERAL” where it occurs in the English translation by Jean Van Heijenoort, where in Relation 17, Van Heijenoort translates as:
Here it is important to understand that here the term “NUMERAL” is not used according to its meaning in English - Van Heijenoort uses the term “NUMERAL” in small capitals to indicate the Gödel number of “numeral”, which was previously defined to be the term that applies to any string of symbols of the formal system of the form
The claim is that while the variable of the
and that Gödel meant that there is some sort of connection between the
(A)
or
(B)
where these imagined functions that are conjured out of nothing are often given a name that includes the word “numeral”.
The obvious error in the claim is the fact that the formal sequences of the form
Besides that, if the domain of
This conflation of language systems can be easily demonstrated, taking the notion (B) above that:
Then we have that, for example:
But then it is also the case that:
where
And so, as before, we then have that:
but although:
we have:
and:
Again, we have a contradiction.
The absurdity of claims of the above sort is mind-bogglingly obvious, yet the authors of such claims seem to be totally unaware of the nonsensical nature of the claims. The irony is that the idea that the variables of the
Weird idea 3. Gödel’s Proposition 5 does not involve Gödel numbering
This involves the claim that Gödel numbering is not required for Gödel’s Proposition 5, that “Goedel numbering does not intrinsically show up at all” in that proposition. Apart from the patently obvious fact that Gödel did not provide a proof of his Proposition 5, instead assuming it to be obvious, the reality is that the statement of the proposition does require Gödel numbering, being:
Proposition V: To every recursive relation R(x1 … xn) there corresponds an n-place relation-string r …
and by Gödel’s definition of relation-string this is:
Proposition V:To every recursive relation R(x1 … xn) there corresponds a Gödel number r, where r is the Gödel number of a formula with n free individual variables ... …
which unambiguously refers to Gödel numbering, confirming that Gödel numbering is an intrinsic prat of the proposition.
Inconsistent systems
Only those who are unaware of basic tenets of mathematics (or those who deliberately ignore them) think that, by carefully choosing the terms and expressions used in an argument in order to avoid any explicit appearance of a contradiction, in some way serves to demonstrate that the system and its assumptions cannot result in any implicit contradiction - that is, that the system is inherently consistent. That, of course is nonsense, and if it can be demonstrated that the assumptions of the system can result in a contradiction, that means that the system is inconsistent and hence any result given by that system is mathematical gibberish. Note that Gödel’s failure to give a detailed argument for his Proposition 5 helps to hide the fact that his assumptions regarding that proposition are intrinsically contradictory.
Note that you can see further wacky ideas and my responses in the comments section below.
At this point we have to acknowledge that we cannot give a brief summary of the details of how this Proposition V is a confusion of different levels of language by the use of this false equivalence. This is because Gödel did not actually give a fully detailed proof of this crucial part of his incompleteness paper - he simply assumed that it was correct, only giving a rough outline of how a proof of that crucial part might proceed, saying in his paper: “We content ourselves here with indicating the proof of this proposition in outline, since it offers no difficulties of principle and is somewhat involved.”
The convicted paedophile ex-professor Peter Smith, although he is a staunch advocate of Gödel’s proof, acknowledges in his paper, PDF Expounding the First Incompleteness Theorem, that:
“Gödel only sketches a proof by induction on the complexity of the definition of the (characteristic function of the) property or relation in terms of definitions by composition and recursion grounding out in the trivial initial functions. The crucial step is just asserted - ‘the processes of definition … (substitution and recursion) can both be formally reproduced in the system P’ … it certainly isn’t spelt out.”
See also Peter Smith’s Gödel Without (Too Many) Tears - Or Not? and PDF A Fundamental Flaw in an Incompleteness Proof by Peter Smith.
This failure to give a fully detailed proof is even more surprising in view of Gödel’s insistence elsewhere on clarity and precision.
And today almost every mathematician/
It might be noted here that Gödel’s incompleteness paper is not the only paper where he made a completely unproven assertion which almost everyone assumed to be correct because of Gödel’s esteemed reputation. In that other paper Gödel made a similar intuitive assertion, but it was eventually proved (some 50 years later) that Gödel’s intuitive assumption stated precisely the opposite of what was actually the case. For details of this see Gödel’s Intuitive Error No.2. Not many mathematicians are aware of this - Gödel’s reputation is still so honored today that most discussions of Gödel’s work skip over this inconvenient detail.
A Simplified explanation of Gödel’s proof and the flaw in the proof
If you are not familiar with the details of Gödel’s proof, I suggest that you either read the simplified explanation of Gödel’s proof on this website, or read the novel The Shackles of Conviction. Both include an explanation of the theorem and the flaw in Gödel’s proof of it in a simplified way that makes it accessible to the general reader.
A step by step walk-through guide to Gödel’s Proof
For anyone who wishes to get to grips with Gödel’s original paper, I have created a walk-through guide to Gödel’s original incompleteness proof, and which is intended to be read alongside the paper. Having looked for such a guide and could find none, I thought it odd that there were no such guides, considering how much other material has been written about Gödel’s proof. So I decided to create this guide to assist anyone else who wishes to become familiar with the details of Gödel’s argument.
A Detailed explanation of the flaw in Gödel’s proof
On the other hand, if you are very familiar with the details of Gödel’s theorem, you will probably also want to see the details of the flaw in Gödel’s proof as covered in the paper:
The Fundamental Flaw in Gödel’s Proof of his Incompleteness Theorem
The paper gives a comprehensive demonstration of the flaw in Gödel’s proof of his incompleteness theorem. The link above is a link to the latest version. Please note that the central argument of the paper remains unchanged throughout the revisions. The revisions have been to make the principles easier to understand. After some requests, the latest version includes a brief summary of the illogical unfounded assumption that the entire proof relies on, so that the reader can have an idea of the substance of the flaw within a few pages. If you want to see the previous versions to check that I have not changed the substance of my demonstration of the flaw in Gödel’s proof, please see the site-map. See also Gödel’s 1934 Undecidability lectures, which, although by then Gödel had three years to reflect on his methods of proof, rather ironically allow a much simpler demonstration of the inherent confusion of language that is involved.
The Flaw and the Substitution function in Gödel’s proof
The webpage Gödel’s Substitution Function describes how Gödel’s incorrect use of a ‘substitution’ function confuses the systems that he is dealing with.
Responses to the demonstration of the flaw in Gödel’s proof
Bertrand Russell remarked:
“If a man is offered a fact which goes against his instincts, he will scrutinize it closely, and unless the evidence is overwhelming, he will refuse to believe it. If, on the other hand, he is offered something which affords a reason for acting in accordance to his instincts, he will accept it even on the slightest evidence.” Bertrand Russell, in Ch. VI: International relations in Roads To Freedom, G. Allen & Unwin 1918.
It might be said that Russell did not go far enough - I would rewrite it as:
If a person is offered a fact which goes against their instincts and beliefs, they will carefully scrutinize the evidence to seek a flaw in it - but if they fail to find any flaw in it, they will not necessarily concede - instead they may simply ignore that evidence, and continue to refuse to believe it. If, on the other hand, they are offered something which in accordance with their instincts and beliefs, they will be inclined to accept it without any detailed examination of any available evidence.
And in the 1950s, Leon Festinger coined the term cognitive dissonance, and remarked: Leon Festinger: “When Prophecy Fails: A Social & Psychological Study of a Modern Group that Predicted the Destruction of the World”, Harper-Torchbooks, 1956, ISBN: 0-06-131132-4. The psychologist Carol Tavris has expanded on Festinger’s work and has written a book on the subject (co-written with Elliot Aronson): “Mistakes were made (but not by me): Why we justify foolish beliefs, bad decisions, and hurtful acts”, Harcourt, 2007.
A man with a conviction is a hard man to change. Tell him you disagree and he turns away. Show him facts or figures and he questions your sources. Appeal to logic and he fails to see your point. But suppose he is presented with evidence, unequivocal and undeniable evidence, that his belief is wrong: what will happen? The individual will frequently emerge, not only unshaken, but even more convinced of the truth of his beliefs than ever before.
And this is precisely what has happened with Gödel’s proof - I have provided a detailed analysis which the vast majority of people reject, even though they cannot find any error in it, while on the other hand, they are perfectly content to accept Gödel’s Proposition V, a crucial assertion in Gödel’s proof, for which Gödel never provided any detailed proof (and neither has anyone else done so).
If you would like to see some of the responses that I have received regarding the demonstration of the flaw in Gödel’s proof, please see Responses to the demonstration of the flaw.
Rationale: Every logical argument must be defined in some language, and every language has limitations. Attempting to construct a logical argument while ignoring how the limitations of language might affect that argument is a bizarre approach. The correct acknowledgment of the interactions of logic and language explains almost all of the paradoxes, and resolves almost all of the contradictions, conundrums, and contentious issues in modern philosophy and mathematics.
Site Mission
Please see the menu for numerous articles of interest. Please leave a comment or send an email if you are interested in the material on this site.
Interested in supporting this site?
You can help by sharing the site with others. You can also donate at
where there are full details.